Regular readers of my blog (and I hope I have some) will be
aware that I have been, from the beginning, trying to set out a novel theory of
literary criticism. The theory of narrative that I have been proposing is based
on the idea that a story is a kind of rhetorical construction and that it argues in favour of two
mutually-exclusive statements about the world at the same time, statements that
I term the ‘thesis’ and the ‘antithesis’. It is the tension between the two opposing world-views that creates conflict. A story
generally ends with the victory of the thesis over the antithesis – although
some stories can finish ambiguously, leaving the issue open. I wrote about this
in my first post, the ‘Preamble’ and I have put the theory into practice a
couple of times since, for instance in the post about James Joyce’s “The Dead”.
In today’s post I am going to try something new, something
that I think may be radical and wholly original and that I suspect may never
have been attempted before – to apply the logic of Predicate Calculus to
narrative. I need first to say something about Predicate Calculus. Predicate
Calculus is a quasi-mathematical formalism, invented by Gottlob Frege and
Charles Pierce in the late nineteenth century, which developed from and
synthesises the older systems of propositional logic and syllogistic logic. The
major advance made by Predicate Calculus is that it introduces the terms Universal Quantifier (represented by a symbol that I cannot put down because Blogspot does not include it as an option)
and Existential Quantifier (ditto previous note):
the first can be interpreted as signifying the clause “For all things in the world..."; the second can be interpreted as signifying "At least one thing in
the world exists such that…” For example, the proposition “All swans are white” can
be put into Predicate Calculus form as “Ax: xS C xW”
which literally means “For all
things in the world, if it is a swan then it is white”. The proposition
“Some swans are black” can be expressed “Ex: xS & ¬xW”
which literally means “Something exists in the world that is a swan and is not
white.”
[Note: because blogspot does not know the symbols for logical operators, this is a slightly fudged description of Predicate Calculus. The Universal Quantifier is actually an upside-down A and the Existential Quantifier a backwards E. The if-then symbol should be a horseshoe facing the other way. If you want a less fudged explanation of Predicate Calculus, you can easily find one elsewhere on the Internet.]
Propositions always come in pairs. A universal proposition
such as “All swans are white” must be false if the existential proposition
“Some swans are black” is true, and vice versa. I believe that the thesis and
the antithesis expressed by a story can be viewed as examples of such paired
propositions. For example, the thesis of Star Wars is “Good always triumphs over evil” and the
antithesis is “Sometimes evil can triumph over good.” Because the Empire is
presented as vastly more powerful than Luke and the Rebels, Luke’s eventual
victory is a strong argument in favour of the thesis. In the film Sleepless
in Seattle, the thesis of the film is
“Everyone is destined to be with his or her true love” and the antithesis of
the films is “Sometimes the obstacles are too great”. In this film, the destined lovers are on opposite sides of America and yet they still get together– the
fact that they successfully find each other is testament to the ‘truth’ of the
thesis. In Macbeth, the thesis of
the play is “Everyone pays for their crimes” and the antithesis is “Sometimes
people get away with murder.” In Macbeth, the witches continually prophecy that Macbeth will escape divine
retribution but, in the final analysis, the witches are unnatural whereas moral consequences are a part of the natural order of things. According to all natural laws, Macbeth must die. The witches’
riddling prophecies contain loopholes and it is through these loopholes that Providence reasserts itself.
The examples I have given above suggest that stories always argue in support of Universal Propositions rather than Existential Propositions. This is
not the case. Sometimes the thesis a story asserts is actually an Existential
Proposition. In Othello, the thesis is
“Sometimes jealousy is unfounded”. The antithesis is “There is always genuine grounds for jealousy.” The fact that Othello, a good if easily gulled man, can
so easily be taken in by Iago’s plotting is an argument in favour of the
antithesis – but it is the thesis that is shown to be true. In Romeo and Juliet, the thesis is “Sometimes the obstacles to true love
are too great” and the antithesis is “Everyone is destined to be with their
true love” – it is the opposite of Sleepless in Seattle in this respect (and in fact the opposite of most other
romantic comedies. One thinks of Something About Mary). The depth and total commitment of Romeo’s and
Juliet’s love for each other is not enough to save them. This is perhaps the significant
difference between comedies and tragedies. Comedies tend to espouse comforting
Universal Propositions – they please because they reassure. Tragedies, by
contrast, tend to embrace the exception rather than the accepted rule and this
is why they disturb.
Regular readers may also have noticed that I generally tend to
come back to the same literary examples in my writing. This is because it is
convenient and I am lazy. Nevertheless, this form of literary analysis can be
applied to all stories, all books, all films and possibly even most poetry.
Recently I saw the Spielberg film Bridge of Spies starring Tom Hanks. I thought the film was great –
perhaps partly because the Coen brothers had input into the script. This film is not immune to analysis of this sort. If one wants, one can interpret Bridge
of Spies in terms of thesis and antithesis. In my view, the film is dedicated to the claim “Enemy spies should
be treated as humanely as we would want the enemy to treat our own combatants.”
The antithesis presented by the film is “Enemy spies are evil and should be
imprisoned forever or executed.” The film treats the Communist foe ambiguously
– sometimes it is represented as an Evil Empire, sometimes as a mirror image of
the American-led Western alliance. I am unsure if the thesis is a Universal or
Existential proposition, but I will say one thing about the film generally. It
does not draw explicit parallels to Guantanomo Bay but one has to wonder if the
compassion extended towards the Russian spy in the film is not something that
should also be extended, in the present day, to the inhabitants of this brutal institution.
The theory of narrative I am proposing can be applied to almost all stories. Stories which resist interpretation in this way tend not to be good stories – they lack cohesion, they lack a central, defining idea. My theory is that the central idea of a story can be expressed as a logical proposition. A story is trying to persuade its audience that its thesis, its moral, is true. The fact that different stories can present contradictory morals evinces the fact that there is no genuine reality behind them, that truth is what we make it. This fact may be depressing but it is undeniable.